Wanganui

Main Menu

  • Creative Destruction
  • Tax Haven
  • Terminal Value
  • First Theorem Of Welfare Economics
  • Debt

Wanganui

Header Banner

Wanganui

  • Creative Destruction
  • Tax Haven
  • Terminal Value
  • First Theorem Of Welfare Economics
  • Debt
First Theorem Of Welfare Economics
Home›First Theorem Of Welfare Economics›Distributive justice and welfare economics

Distributive justice and welfare economics

By Judy Grier
December 6, 2017
0
0



A fundamental concern of welfare economics, like other evaluative ethical theories, is the assessment of the goodness of a given state of affairs. In the context of an economic survey, it is advisable to describe very simply a state of affairs in terms of a given feasible distribution of goods among the individuals constituting the economy considered. In the appreciation of the distribution of goods which is realized, an evaluation criterion must obviously come into play. A criterion which has greatly preoccupied the economy of well-being is that of the efficiency of Pareto – named after the sociologist. Italian Vilfredo Pareto.

Before defining the Pareto efficiency, it is useful to specify what is now called the Pareto principle. The Pareto principle requires that, given two social states (or allocations, in the present context) a and b, if a is Pareto greater than b in the sense that everyone is better in a than in b, then a is better condition than b.

Any social state a will be said to be Pareto efficient, if there is no other possible state b which is Pareto greater than a. We still need to clarify what we mean by the term better off, a question which is facilitated by the notion of utility function.

It is assumed that each person derives some utility from the batch of products assigned to him by each possible allocation, defined as a set of batches of products, one batch for each person in the economy. If the utility that it obtains from its batch of products under an allocation a is greater than the utility that it obtains from its batch of products under another allocation b, then we will say that it is better with the allocation a than with the allowance b. And if everyone is better, in this sense, under allocation a than under allocation b, then a is Pareto-greater than b.

Welfare economics is also very much concerned with the notion of social welfare function (SWF). Considering any possible allocation a, a SWF associates a number W with a, which is supposed to reflect the overall welfare produced by allocation a. Typically, W would depend on the utility that each person derives from the product bundle assigned to them in the allocation in question. This utility is assumed to be ordinal, that is to say, imbued only with the property of classification. In addition, individual public services are not assumed to be interpersonal comparable. Finally, SWF W is assumed to be Pareto inclusive, which simply means that all things being equal, if a person’s utility increases, overall well-being will also increase. By choosing between other possible allocations, the welfare economy follows the cause of this allocation which maximizes a social welfare function of the type just described. One can easily verify that any allocation which maximizes such a welfare function is also Pareto-efficient.

Are there any institutional arrangements that we know of that are compatible with the emergence of effective Pareto results? Scholars familiar with Adam Smith’s “Invisible Hand” account of a market will immediately see a link between allocation ordered by a competitive market and Pareto efficiency.

Indeed, the content of the so-called first theorem of welfare economics is precisely that under certain well-defined conditions, a competitive equilibrium is Pareto efficient. (Secular interpretations of the theorem have led to lazy and inaccurate idealizations of the market as an institution.) But the first theorem, as Amartya Sen has pointed out, is entirely devoid of the kind of ethical meaning one would seek if there was an equal concern for the allocation caused by a competitive equilibrium. It is Pareto effective, but could well be deeply inegalitarian.

To see this, consider a two-person corporation in which Person 1’s share of the social dividend from an efficient allocation is a fraction x, and Person 2’s share is (1-x). If we increase x, person 1’s situation will be better, but person 2’s situation will be worse. If we reduce x, person 2 will be better off and person 1 will be worse off. In other words, there is no change in x, which can improve the situation for both people.

Equivalently, the result (x, 1-x) is Pareto efficient. But this must be valid for all x fractions. So there can be an infinite number of Pareto-efficient results (because there is an infinite number of x fractions), and welfare economics offers little prescriptive guidance for choosing between them. We will explore this question in a little more detail in a later article, with specific reference to Amartya Sen’s work in this regard. One of Sen’s most distinctive contributions to normative economics has been his critique of the theoretical foundations of welfare economics, a critique that exposes the inability of welfare economics to deal in a meaningful way. significant distribution problems. This, as we will see later, has a lot to do with the depleted and purely utility-based information upon which the welfare economy relies.

Let me conclude with a reading tip for anyone interested in exploring the issues noted above in more depth. A wonderfully lucid treatment of the subject under discussion is available in an essay written in 1975 by Professor Hal Varian of the University of California, Berkeley, entitled “Distributive Justice, Welfare Economics, and The Theory of Fairness.” , which was published in the journal Philosophy And Public Affairs, I took a lot of inspiration from Varian in writing this story, but there is no substitute for the original, which I highly recommend to the interested reader.

S. Subramanian is an economist, comments are welcome at [email protected]

To subscribe to Mint newsletters

* Enter a valid email

* Thank you for subscribing to our newsletter.

Never miss a story! Stay connected and informed with Mint. Download our app now !!

The subjects



Related posts:

  1. Request revolving credit? Responsible and affordable from 4.5%
  2. Credit without guarantor
  3. Definition of Maurice Allais
  4. Definition of welfare economics

Recent Posts

  • XPeng Stock: Anchored in Valuation, Not Speculation (NYSE: XPEV)
  • Balenciaga’s trashed sneakers divide opinion and tap into fashion history
  • US States Struggle to Replace Tax Revenue from Fossil Fuels | News, Sports, Jobs
  • MarketInk: Newsradio KOGO Wins Regional Edward R. Murrow Award
  • Scarlet Witch Fills Out The Original MCU Hulk Arc

Archives

  • May 2022
  • April 2022
  • March 2022
  • February 2022
  • January 2022
  • December 2021
  • November 2021
  • October 2021
  • September 2021
  • August 2021
  • July 2021
  • June 2021
  • May 2021
  • April 2021
  • March 2021
  • February 2021
  • January 2021
  • December 2020
  • November 2020
  • October 2020
  • September 2020
  • August 2020
  • July 2020
  • June 2020
  • April 2020
  • March 2020
  • February 2020
  • January 2020
  • December 2019
  • November 2019
  • October 2019
  • September 2019
  • July 2019
  • June 2019
  • April 2019
  • February 2019
  • January 2019
  • September 2018
  • December 2017
  • October 2017
  • March 2017
  • February 2017
  • December 2016
  • August 2016
  • May 2016
  • April 2016
  • October 2015
  • May 2015
  • April 2015
  • November 2014
  • September 2013
  • August 2010

Categories

  • Creative Destruction
  • Debt
  • First Theorem Of Welfare Economics
  • Tax Haven
  • Terminal Value
  • Terms and Conditions
  • Privacy Policy